Given that artists often have views about the function(s) of art and often intend their artworks to have that function, I wonder whether we can just dismiss the approach of determining the function of art through looking at artists’ intentions concerning that function.[This paper is based on comments delivered at the ASA Pacific Division conference in 2013 in response to Justine Kingsbury’s paper “Function Claims About Art:What (If Anything) Makes Them True.”]
Here is one
possible solution to the problem of how to determine the proper function of art
while focusing on artists’ intentions. We begin with three plausible propositions. (1) The
proper functions of any one artwork include minimally the function or functions
intended by the creator. (2) The proper
functions of any particular type of artwork, at any particular time, are
whatever functions most art makers attribute to their artworks in that genre at that time. (3) The proper functions of art in general
consist of the various functions listed in the previous group. (I will not, in
the end, advocate this approach: but it
is a nice starting point.) Carlson and
Parsons in their book Functional Beauty
do not talk about the function of art.
However, they do talk about the function of a pipe cleaner. They comment that a pipe cleaner may have
some functions today which were not intended by its original designer. Art works too may have new functions. We might then say that the functions of any
particular artefact (artworks included) can
also include (in addition to the intended function) whatever fits what the user intends its function to be, as long
as it serves that function well. A pipe
cleaner serves the function of material for children’s crafts quite well, and
is intended to serve that function by some of its users, and so we can say that
this is one of its current functions even though it was originally intended
just for cleaning pipes.
But what of the
distinction between proper and accidental function? A belt buckle might accidentally function as
a shield when it deflects a bullet. However,
a proper function has to be more than accidental: it has to be at least part of a practice. This does not mean that the class-room pipe
cleaner usage is not a proper function. When
pipe cleaners function as play-room tools this is part of a regular practice
and not merely accidental. We could also
say that a function of art is to support a repressive regime. But is that its proper function or is this
function merely accidental? This is a
hard question since art works may function in this way systematically in particular
societies, which seems to make it a proper function. I will return to this question later.
Some people
believe that the best way to talk about art’s proper function is to talk about
it as something biological, for example on the analogy to a heart. A heart’s proper function is to pump
blood. But how far does the analogy
go? Isn’t interesting that although
there is nearly universal agreement concerning the proper function of the heart
(although there may be debates in the margins) there is practically none
concerning the proper function of art.
We cannot get much help from biological analogies in trying to determine
whether the proper function of art is, for example, to support a repressive
regime. The say that this is not part
of art’s proper function to to go beyond scientific knowledge and beyond
analogies to proper functions in biology.
Some might think (as Kingsbury has suggested to me in a letter) that
supporting a regime, although a function of art, is not a function of art qua
art. However, this then moves us away
from just talking about biology-like functions to the question of defining art,
which I think is the real question at issue here anyway. That is, questions about the proper function
of art are really, despite their science-like look, philosophical questions
about the essence or proper definition of art.
On my view, when
we think of the proper function of a thing qua that thing we are thinking about
what should be. That is, when people ask “what is the
function of art qua art” they are asking what should art (and thus artists) be
trying to do. This is very much unlike
asking about the function of something biological, like a heart. Function questions in regards to social
institutions and the concepts tied to them look to the future, i.e. look to possible
reform or possible activity. Claims about the proper function of art are
normative claims about the direction of art. Dennis Dutton in his book The Art Instinct famously argued that art took a wrong turn in the
20th century, away from its proper function, a function established
in Pleistocene times. However, the
proper function of art is much more flexible and changeable than that. There can even be many competing proper
functions of art. It is because Dutton
had a vision of the essence of art, and therefore about where art should be
going, and not because of any knowledge he had about prehistoric practices,
that he could comfortably speak of art as taking a wrong turn. Following Plato
(which of course is an unusual thing to do these days…but it works here), we
could say that the proper function is the function that allows the object or
genre in question best to participate in the good (where that is taken to be
the sum good for a cultural unit, a society, humanity in general, or even some
larger unit). That’s why we would reject
saying that supporting a repressive regime is part of the function of art qua
art.
However, although
I am attracted to the Platonic approach mentioned I would relativize it and
situate it within a historical, rather than an ahistorical (i.e. Platonic),
dialectic. The proper function of
architecture would be the function that best realizes the good (in society,
say) at that time in history, i.e. as response to the previous best
understandings of the essence of architecture. When Robert Venturi defined
architecture as a decorated shed he was saying that this is the proper function
of architecture relativized to his own cultural context (he even says that this
is the definition his firm is working with now). Call this the relativized idealist view of
proper function. The proper function, on
this view, might be quite different from the standard function. One evokes the proper function when one wants
to make the world better. It might also
be quite different from the intended function although it would be the intended
function for anyone who held this theory of the proper function, for example
Venturi himself. This of course would be
very different from looking at whether art promotes gene survival, causes women
to be sexually attracted to male artists, or confers advantages on social
groups. All of these things can be functions of art, but not necessarily the or
even a proper function since, for example, whatever confers advantage on a gene
or social group may not be good in a broader scheme of things or may not be
good for us now. Why should we assume
that the or a proper function of art should be whatever function one of the
ancestors of art had insofar as it promoted survival amongst hominids at some
time in the past? Moreover, limiting
discussion of proper function to the relativized idealist model focuses on what
is actually of concern to artists. Those
who understand the proper function of art in biological terms generally
understand it in terms of how it will promote certain genes. Yet, artists are not concerned (consciously
at least) about promoting their genes. Function
claims about concepts like art, democracy, knowledge, and so forth (that is, all
the things we like to debate about in philosophy) are grounded in overall
visions about what makes a society, or human existence generally, good. A function claim about art tells us how we
can use art to fully realize our ideals for society or human existence. Function claims about art are deeply normative.
How, then, does
one decide between two function claims about art? If one is normative and the other is merely
descriptive then both can be true and we do not have to worry about deciding
between then. They are just two
different kinds of claims about two different kinds of things. However, we should bear in mind that many
supposed descriptive claims are actually secretly normative. For example, if someone says, like Clive Bell,
that all things correctly called art give aesthetic ecstasy in response to
significant form, one could say that this is really a normative rather than a
descriptive claim about the function of art.
When both of the
competing claims are normative, then, since we are talking about competing
ideals, and systems of ideals at that, there does not seem to be any way to
resolve the debate by way of a correspondence theory of truth. However, a pragmatist theory of truth would
simply ask us to look at which theory works best: i.e. which reverberates most strongly in the
culture, which has the power to generate new valuable work in that art-form,
and so forth. Robert Venturi’s
definition of architecture in which he gave the function of architecture in a
normative way as “a work of architecture is a decorated shed,” was extremely
powerful in that it contributed to the founding of a new school of architecture
which is still influential today. One
could say that it therefore fit the pragmatist criterion for truth. Remember that, on this view, truth is
relativized to context, so that Venturi’s account of architecture was more
successful than that of Gideon during the
1970s, but it would have been less successful in another social context,
for example in the context in which Gideon’s definition was successful. When it comes to functionalist definitions,
not everything is possible at every time. Choosing between different functionalist
claims is a matter of choosing what future one wishes to project for one’s
group, society or for humanity itself. The definitions that work best are the
ones that work over the long run. Those who chose a Stalinist ideal of
socialism found that this choice did not work over the long run in their
functionalist definition of democracy, or of socialism for that matter, and so the
related functionalist definition of art (e.g. social realism) also failed over
the long run, although admittedly it had some limited success in the short run.
“The long run” however can be defined in different ways, and even the longest
runs are small when looked at from a grander perspective. Perhaps the best that we can hope for from a
functionalist definition of art is that it captures what is living and has real
potential in the best art of today, projecting out to some sort of “long run.”
Functionalist
definitions of art, on this account, are pretty much the same as what Morris Weitz
referred to as honorific definitions, which are significantly more important,
at least for artists, than debates over what George Dickie referred to as
descriptive definitions. (Treating functionalist definitions as honorific
definitions resolves one of the problems Justine mentioned about functionalist
definitions since honorific definitions are not intended to cover all things
called art, and thus resist refutation by counterexample.) In any case, we need
to bear in mind that debates over the proper function of art are quite a bit
different from debates over the proper function of a can-opener, and certainly
than debates over the proper function of a heart. “Art” is what W. B. Gallie
referred to as an essentially contested concept. When we debate over the essence of art we are
debating over its function in a normative sense. As I have suggested, debates
over the function of art, are ultimately aspects of larger normative debates
over what it is to be human or even what it is to be, i.e. debates between worldviews. By contrast, debates over the proper function
of a can-opener are usually short and philosophically uninteresting.
In sum, whether
there is a logic of proper functions
with regard to essentially contested concepts such as “art” (as opposed to say
bodily organs such as the heart) is an open question which may only be resolved
by not limiting ourselves to strictly science-centered notions of functionality
and incorporating philosophical notions, such as for example that of honorific
definition.