Goodman's famous "When is Art?" appeared in his
1978 book Ways of Worldmaking. The chapter seems at
first to be mainly directed against formalists such as Clive Bell and more
importantly, probably, Clement Greenberg, although neither of these are
mentioned (he simply refers to a group of theorists and artists which he calls
"purists" and sometimes "formalists"). Goodman wants
to show that the purists are wrong that the abstract art they favor does not
symbolize. He has a broader notion of "symbolize" such that
something can fail to represent or express but could still symbolize if it
exemplifies. All of this mainly seems to be just a matter of semantics,
Goodman having a much broader use of "symbol" than the purists. As we shall see, however, this is far from the case.
A more important target for the essay is the work of Arthur
Danto, although Goodman never mentions Danto. (Surely they knew each
other: New York is not that far from
Boston). Both Goodman and Danto are
trying to account for found art and conceptual art as well as for highly
abstract minimalist art. A useful way to see their distinction and
implicit disagreement can show, in part, how Goodman leads us on a path that seems
at first to be more world-connected than Danto's and hence more useful for the
project of everyday aesthetics. In fact,
the two can be used to supplement each other since Goodman focuses on the
sensuous and directly apparent aspect of experience, whereas Danto focuses on
the cultural-meaning and not immediately apparent aspect.
For Goodman, something is art when it functions as art, and something functions as art when its exhibits an unspecified number of symptoms of the aesthetic (although the most important of these is exemplification.) Thus objects, such as paintings, can move several times in their lifetime in an out of arthood. It follows from this that they can also move in and out of the everyday. Goodman of course did not realize, or at least, did not mention this.
Unfortunately, when they are out of arthood they are also out of the realm of the aesthetic since Goodman doesn’t really take into account non-art aesthetics.
Take for example a rock picked up in a driveway (Goodman's example). Goodman believes that when the rock is in the driveway it has no aesthetic properties (this of course cannot be accepted by everyday aesthetics) but that when it is put on a pedestal in an art gallery it comes to exemplify certain properties (and so, is symbolic even if it does not represent or express). In doing this it comes to function as art.
The relevance of this for everyday aesthetics is that there
can be a realm between non-art and art that is aesthetic but not enough so, or
in enough ways, to be art. I doubt that
Goodman would have agreed with this (given his metaphysical strictures against possibility)
but, as I see it, the rock can have potential aesthetic properties which are
actualized in the experience of someone who looks at it with an artist’s eye,
and then those properties can be full actualized when the rock achieves art
status in the context of a museum exhibit where it is displayed as art and thus
can fully function as art.
Goodman does not define art in terms of necessary and
sufficient conditions, but he does talk about what he calls "symptoms of
the aesthetic" by which he means symptoms of arthood: these are
syntactic density, semantic density, relative repleteness, exemplification and
multiple and complex reference. There is no need here to go into detail
about these, except to mention that relative repleteness means that a line in a
Hokusai painting is richer in meaning than a similar line on a Stock Exchange
chart. I suspect that all of the symptoms of the aesthetic refer
basically to one thing: it is the same intuition expressed in different
ways. The conditions of syntactic and semantic density are both described in terms of very fine discriminations, as is also relative repleteness. Goodman himself suggests that all of the symptoms are one when he says that they all "focus attention on rather than, or at least along with, what [the work]
refers to." We cannot simply look through the symbol to its referent
as we would in the case of a traffic light or a science text. We must
"attend constantly to the symbol itself." We know something is art if it calls attention to the properties it exemplifies in a fine-grained way. That pretty much sums up Goodman's theory.
Danto (I am speaking here just of his view in "The
Artworld") would hold that for the art to be art it is not sufficient that
it be exhibited in a gallery by an artist, although this can contribute to its
arthood. It must be seen as art by someone with suitable art historical
and art theoretical knowledge, i.e. seen under the appropriate concept of art.
It must also have some part that is seen with what he calls the “is of artistic
identification.” This special "is" might better have been called "the is of imaginative identification" since a child sees his hobbyhorse as a horse imaginatively and yet this does not mean he or she sees it as art. The "is of artistic identification" is necessary but not sufficient for art.
So whereas Goodman can be seen as expanding the formalist conception of art (initiated by Kant and expanded by Bell to include relations of lines and colors) to include new material (for example texture and the type of material used), Danto can be seen as rejecting it. Whereas Goodman thinks art calls on us to attend quite carefully to its many exhibited referential features, Danto thinks that we need to attend to things that are not exhibited (at least directly in the work) for example art history, art theory, the intended meaning of the artist, the title, and physical artworld placement (i.e. in a gallery or museum). As I have suggested, I think both are right about this.
So whereas Goodman can be seen as expanding the formalist conception of art (initiated by Kant and expanded by Bell to include relations of lines and colors) to include new material (for example texture and the type of material used), Danto can be seen as rejecting it. Whereas Goodman thinks art calls on us to attend quite carefully to its many exhibited referential features, Danto thinks that we need to attend to things that are not exhibited (at least directly in the work) for example art history, art theory, the intended meaning of the artist, the title, and physical artworld placement (i.e. in a gallery or museum). As I have suggested, I think both are right about this.
An interesting feature of Goodman is that art's function is
cognitive and, as cognitive, it does relate very much to the world, through
various forms of reference. Danto's approach also provides reference to
the world but in his case it is through aboutness or meaning. Two paintings can be visually
indistinguishable, but their titles, for example Newton’s First Law and Newton’s
Second Law, provide external reference and hence meaning. (The body is in fact unimportant since except as a receptacle. This can be seen by the fact that two different works can have the same body, or at least a visually identical one.) In addition to the titles there is
whatever else might go into the intended meaning of the creator.
Both Goodman and Danto might well admire an all-red painting, but for Goodman the key is in how the artist has drawn our attention to the particular quality of redness and to all sorts of other exhibited features. Goodman does allow, however, some external reference through his notion of metaphorical exemplification as well as through the fact that the property of redness is shared by all of the other red things in the world. Danto focuses instead on the way in which we see the painting based on our knowledge of art history, the intentions of the painter, the title and so forth.
For Goodman it is what you see that gives you at least indirect reference, i.e. exemplification. (Denotative reference plays only a small role in Goodman’s theory of art.) For Goodman, even work that is entirely abstract can exemplify its properties, properties which are shared by objects outside the artwork. Thus the entire distinction between properties that are intrinsic and ones that are extrinsic seems to dissolve (not entirely though). Goodman's approach explains why, after seeing a show by a good artist, we tend to see things in the world in terms of the works. He in a sense captures the dynamic interaction of art and world in a way that Danto does not. But then Danto provides captures something about that in a way Goodman does not. In short, for Danto artworld knowledge can enter into that which is expressed or even exemplified by a work of art.
Both Goodman and Danto might well admire an all-red painting, but for Goodman the key is in how the artist has drawn our attention to the particular quality of redness and to all sorts of other exhibited features. Goodman does allow, however, some external reference through his notion of metaphorical exemplification as well as through the fact that the property of redness is shared by all of the other red things in the world. Danto focuses instead on the way in which we see the painting based on our knowledge of art history, the intentions of the painter, the title and so forth.
For Goodman it is what you see that gives you at least indirect reference, i.e. exemplification. (Denotative reference plays only a small role in Goodman’s theory of art.) For Goodman, even work that is entirely abstract can exemplify its properties, properties which are shared by objects outside the artwork. Thus the entire distinction between properties that are intrinsic and ones that are extrinsic seems to dissolve (not entirely though). Goodman's approach explains why, after seeing a show by a good artist, we tend to see things in the world in terms of the works. He in a sense captures the dynamic interaction of art and world in a way that Danto does not. But then Danto provides captures something about that in a way Goodman does not. In short, for Danto artworld knowledge can enter into that which is expressed or even exemplified by a work of art.
So Goodman could accommodate Danto's
insight, and Danto Goodman’s. But artworld knowledge does not play such
an important role in Goodman as it does in Danto. Actually it seems to play no role at all.
Danto stresses the "is of artistic identification" which, as I suggested above, seems more like an "is of imaginative identification" or
that, plus, seeing the object as art. Goodman allows for metaphorical
exemplification, and hence also for imaginative identification. However,
he has no role for an is of artistic identification where it is required that
we see the object as art according to a theory of art. (Both Goodman and Danto draw on Weitz. Goodman, like Weitz, moves away from defining art, replacing "What is art?" with another question. Danto, like Weitz, thinks that the conflict of theories of art is really important even though the conflict of philosophical theories of art ended when Warhol and he discovered what art really is. The importance of theories continues rather in further complexities of the style matrix.)
Another important difference between the two concerns what happens when the artwork leaves the art gallery. For Danto it is still art if it is purchased, taken home and perceived by someone with suitable art historical knowledge. What is not clear is what happens if the Warhol Brillo Box is taken to a warehouse where it is indistinguishable from the Brillo boxes there: is it still art? (Danto at one point imagines the Brillo Box just is an appropriated Brillo box from the factory. That version of Brillo Box, not Warhol's version, would then be totally indistinguishable from the other Brillo boxes, assuming that its history of origin is forgotten, or someone switches it with a real Brillo box by accident.)
Danto sometimes talks like Dickie: once art, always art, and therefore Brillo Box is still art out of the gallery, as though once it has been displayed as art in the art gallery it cannot stop being so...even if it is impossible to locate it amongst its indiscernible counterparts in the warehouse. (But at other times he takes the opposite position holding the Brillo Box is reduced to its real counterpart once it is taken out of the gallery. Danto: you can't have it both ways!)
Goodman however says that once it ceases to function as art it is no art. Well he hedges on that a bit (more than a bit): he says a Rembrandt may still be a Rembrandt after it has been taken out of the museum and used as a blanket. Yet under these post-apocalyptic conditions it would no longer be functioning as art, and so it would not be art, unless you could say it had the potential to once again be art...which, as we saw, would go against Goodman's spare metaphysics.)
But the question of when it is art is really more important, for him, than "what is art." It is art when it functions as art, which does not happen when it functions as a blanket. So one of Warhol's Brillo Boxes taken to the warehouse no longer functions as art and hence is no longer art for Goodman, which seems right to me, until I think of the curator who has been desperately looking for his stolen art, and at last finds it hidden in plain sight in the warehouse. She is not going to say, "well it is no longer a work of art." So that is a problem for both Danto and Goodman.
Another important difference between the two concerns what happens when the artwork leaves the art gallery. For Danto it is still art if it is purchased, taken home and perceived by someone with suitable art historical knowledge. What is not clear is what happens if the Warhol Brillo Box is taken to a warehouse where it is indistinguishable from the Brillo boxes there: is it still art? (Danto at one point imagines the Brillo Box just is an appropriated Brillo box from the factory. That version of Brillo Box, not Warhol's version, would then be totally indistinguishable from the other Brillo boxes, assuming that its history of origin is forgotten, or someone switches it with a real Brillo box by accident.)
Danto sometimes talks like Dickie: once art, always art, and therefore Brillo Box is still art out of the gallery, as though once it has been displayed as art in the art gallery it cannot stop being so...even if it is impossible to locate it amongst its indiscernible counterparts in the warehouse. (But at other times he takes the opposite position holding the Brillo Box is reduced to its real counterpart once it is taken out of the gallery. Danto: you can't have it both ways!)
Goodman however says that once it ceases to function as art it is no art. Well he hedges on that a bit (more than a bit): he says a Rembrandt may still be a Rembrandt after it has been taken out of the museum and used as a blanket. Yet under these post-apocalyptic conditions it would no longer be functioning as art, and so it would not be art, unless you could say it had the potential to once again be art...which, as we saw, would go against Goodman's spare metaphysics.)
But the question of when it is art is really more important, for him, than "what is art." It is art when it functions as art, which does not happen when it functions as a blanket. So one of Warhol's Brillo Boxes taken to the warehouse no longer functions as art and hence is no longer art for Goodman, which seems right to me, until I think of the curator who has been desperately looking for his stolen art, and at last finds it hidden in plain sight in the warehouse. She is not going to say, "well it is no longer a work of art." So that is a problem for both Danto and Goodman.
So, what is the value of this debate to everyday aesthetics? It is not explicit but rather lies in the gradual evaporation of the distinction between that which is intrinsic and that which is extrinsic in formalist art (especially for Goodman), combined with his view that art is essentially cognitive. Because art's significance goes beyond representation and expression to also include exemplification, including both literal and metaphorical exemplification, and both of sensually evident and experientially somewhat hidden cultural properties, this draws our attention to aesthetic qualities of everyday life.
Goodman’s expansion of "formalist" to include not
only relations of lines and colors but also texture and material, and perhaps
much more (insofar as the intrinsic/extrinsic distinction does dissolve)
encourages us to focus on art features in a much more multi-sensuous way than
is allowed by traditional formalism.
Bear in mind that, strictly speaking, Goodman has to be against the aesthetics of everyday life: he seems to make no distinction between art and aesthetic, and he seems to reduce the aesthetic to the artistic, so that the aesthetic is only within the realm of art. But again, as anything can move in or out of the realm of art, depending on how it functions, one could imagine an in between realm, the realm of everyday aesthetics where some, but not the sufficient number or intensity of symptoms of “the aesthetic” (which is to say, of arthood) are present.
Bear in mind that, strictly speaking, Goodman has to be against the aesthetics of everyday life: he seems to make no distinction between art and aesthetic, and he seems to reduce the aesthetic to the artistic, so that the aesthetic is only within the realm of art. But again, as anything can move in or out of the realm of art, depending on how it functions, one could imagine an in between realm, the realm of everyday aesthetics where some, but not the sufficient number or intensity of symptoms of “the aesthetic” (which is to say, of arthood) are present.
A big difference between Goodman and Danto here is that Danto lays a lot of emphasis on imaginative seeing and Goodman seems to lay none at all. The “is” of artistic representation, since it can also be applied to what the child does in pretending that a stick is a horse, plays no role in Goodman, except perhaps in the domain of metaphorical exemplification. Once the “is” is let in, and metaphorical exemplification emphasized we can see that the artist, in looking imaginatively at both her subject matter and her materials is, through the process of creative work, able ultimately to make something that, in Danto’s words, embodies meaning.
My view of everyday aesthetics would incorporate both
insights even though neither were actually applied by their authors beyond the world of art. One of the reasons for this is that neither
Danto nor Goodman seemed to pay much attention to the artist’s perspective in
the creative process. (Yuriko Saito has
pointed out how most philosophers,
certainly in the analytic tradition, have neglected the creator’s
perspective. Exceptions are Nietzsche
and Dewey, and, oddly given his idealism, Collingwood, who is one of those rare
philosophers who thinks a lot about the relationship between the artist and her
materials and subject matter in the studio.)
But this, of course, requires seeing the relationship between everyday aesthetics and art aesthetics as being dynamic and interactional. It would reject those views of everyday aesthetics which see the everyday as totally detached from art every bit as much as it would reject those who, like Danto in some moods, see art totally detached from the everyday. For Danto, if Rauschenberg’s Bed is stripped of its paint it becomes a mere bed again, and if Warhol’s Brillo Box is taken out of the gallery and, even more generally, out of the artworld context, it too loses all of its art-relevant properties, which are the only aesthetic properties of much interest to Danto. My view, perhaps closer to Goodman on this point, is that the materials taken up by artists in the creative process contain aesthetic properties already, and that these are transformed in the creative process. Dewey says that art refines and intensifies everyday experience. This is how that is done: the artist in the creative process refines and intensifies art-like aesthetic properties already there in the non-art world, both the ones favored by Danto and the ones favored by Goodman.
But this, of course, requires seeing the relationship between everyday aesthetics and art aesthetics as being dynamic and interactional. It would reject those views of everyday aesthetics which see the everyday as totally detached from art every bit as much as it would reject those who, like Danto in some moods, see art totally detached from the everyday. For Danto, if Rauschenberg’s Bed is stripped of its paint it becomes a mere bed again, and if Warhol’s Brillo Box is taken out of the gallery and, even more generally, out of the artworld context, it too loses all of its art-relevant properties, which are the only aesthetic properties of much interest to Danto. My view, perhaps closer to Goodman on this point, is that the materials taken up by artists in the creative process contain aesthetic properties already, and that these are transformed in the creative process. Dewey says that art refines and intensifies everyday experience. This is how that is done: the artist in the creative process refines and intensifies art-like aesthetic properties already there in the non-art world, both the ones favored by Danto and the ones favored by Goodman.
Further Thoughts on Danto vs. Goodman
The battle between Danto and Goodman is between seeing the body (the work of art)
through atmosphere, where the body is basically unimportant, to seeing and
looking at the body with emphasis on discriminating and appreciating fine
distinctions concerning properties (in an enhanced formalist fashion) with
little or no attention paid to background context. So this debate is a variation of the
contextualist vs. formalist debate that we all the time in art circles (although the contextualists are the current winners).
Both Danto and Goodman are thinking of Ad Rhinehart and
other "purists" of the time. Both think
that the purists are wrong, and both spend considerable energy proving them wrong! This makes reading both philosophers sometimes seem dated: who really cares now that the purists were wrong? The important point however is why they are wrong. Danto thinks
they are wrong because what he calls "Reality Theory" (based ultimately on Bell and Fry, Fry being the one who is quoted by Danto) is wrong. For Danto, purists fail to see that they are using the “is”
of artistic identification. They fail to
see the background presence of the style matrix.
Goodman also believes that the purists are
wrong, but this time because the purists do not see that there is a third kind
of reference in art, even art that is not representational or expressive.
So they do not see that their work actually does symbolize, i.e. it symbolizes through exemplification. Looking at storeroom samples helps us see this. (It is interesting to me, an everyday aesthetician, that Goodman goes to everyday life for his key example and his fundamental insight. Of course the path for this was already cleared by Wittgenstein.) It is not that the painting is just like a
sample swatch. Both exemplify, but the
painting has other symptoms of the aesthetic as well.
One needs to have more than just exemplification.
Danto’s critic makes the painting art
because he sees it as art through his/her appropriate art historical
knowledge. Goodman’s critic sees the
painting as art because she sees that it functions as art and sees that
because she can see that, when looking at it closely, it exemplifies certain
properties. How do you know that it
does? The key is that it is in an art
museum. Being in the art museum draws attention (in audience members) to “formal”
properties, whereas if it were in another museum, say a geology museum, this
would draw attention to other properties.
So for both Danto and Goodman being in a museum, although not a sufficient
or a necessary condition for art, is practically a guarantee of
arthood because it directs a certain kind of seeing. Danto’s kind of seeing is a “seeing as” based
on background knowledge. Goodman’s kind
of seeing is more like that of Hume’s good judge: it involves delicate discrimination. Goodman’s definition of art in terms of five
symptoms emphasizes looking at it in terms of what he calls "intransparency." Background knowledge could even be a hindrance to this.
So what should we do, follow Danto or follow
Goodman? The answer is to follow
both, even though you probably can't do so at the same time. They both provide a great way to see and understand art.
Note also the impact on seeing
outside the museum, i.e. in everyday life. Danto is looking
for thick perception, as Allen Carlson would put it, Goodman for thin, but very
thorough, perception. The Goodmanian
might be made aware of all of the ways in which subtle discrimination can work
in everyday life. The Dantoian critic
will help us be aware of how context can help us see things through at
atmosphere of knowledge of history and concept.