I have long thought that aesthetics is short-changed by philosophy
in its relation to ethics. This is
almost always the case, but sometimes a philosopher will begin to grant its
importance. Instructive in this regard
is a passage in William James’ classic work “The Moral Philosophy and the Moral
Life.” There, he divides moral
philosophy into three questions, of which he notes that the psychological is,
for most, the only question. The main
point of the essay has to do with the other two questions, the metaphysical and
the casuistical (he deals with each in
sequence). But I think sometimes the
revealing stuff comes at the beginning.
Here (on the psychological question) he notes that the usual debate is between
the doctor of divinity and the popular science enthusiast, for whom the question
of ethics is really one of whether there is a unique faculty of conscience or
whether such a faculty is superstition in the face of environmental determinism. He calls it the debate between the intuitionist
and the evolutionist. It still goes on
today. James seems to associate the
second school with the utilitarians (Bentham, Mill, Bain). Utilitarians, he argues, hold that ideals must have
arisen from association with simple bodily pleasures and pains. (He must not be thinking seriously about Mill’s
modification of Bentham’s utilitarianism where quality gains over quantity.) But, James argues, we cannot explain all our
sentiments and judgments in this way. There
are “secondary affections” that relate our impressions in a different way than
by association. He lists a number of
these, from “the love of drunkenness” to “the passion of poetry.” These cannot
be wholly explained by association or utility, even though they might go with
other things that can be so explained.
He sees these things as originating not in environmental conditions but
in brain structure, and he thinks that a vast number of our moral perceptions
are of this kind. The passion for music figures as highly here as a “sense for abstract justice” and a love of “higher philosophical
consistencies.” He speaks further of “the feeling of the inward dignity of certain spiritual attitudes, as
peace, serenity, simplicity, veracity” which he finds “quite inexplicable
except by an innate preference….for its own sake.” I would argue that these “spiritual attitudes” can be seen, at
least in the cases of peace, serenity and simplicity, as aesthetic
qualities. (Why not veracity too?) James then makes the aesthetic theme explicit
when he says “The nobler thing tastes
better.” Moreover, he argues, although consequences
may “teach us what things are wicked,”
they do not explain what we consider “mean
and vulgar.” We are disgusted, for example, when the
husband who shoots his wife’s lover and then makes up with her, and with a utopia
based on one person’s lonely torture. He
is particularly impressed by recent condemnations by Tolstoy, Ballamy and Guyau of punitive forms of
retributive justice. Such “subtleties of the
moral sensibility” go “beyond the law of association” as much as “the
delicacies of sentiment” (note the use of this term so closely associated with Hume's theory of taste) as between a pair of lovers that goes beyond mere norms
of etiquette in the courting process. In short, his claim seems to be at least in part that the higher moral considerations, at least the ones that go beyond "commonplace moral maxims" are basically aesthetic.
James assumes that these judgments are based on “subtle
brain-born feelings,” insisting that “inward forces are certainly at work” in
all of these secondary cases. But then
he follows this with the claim that “all the higher, more penetrating ideals
are revolutionary.” I wonder why the higher,
more penetrating ideals would necessarily be attached to subtle brain-born
phenomena as opposed to environmental based phenomena or a combination of both. But let us set this issue aside and continue with his argument.
James goes on: “They [such ideals] present themselves far less in the
guise of effects of past experiences than in that of probable causes of future
experience.” This point seems to veer
off from talk of subtle events in the brain, the point being simply that the environment can also be forced to bend to our
own needs as well. He concludes that our
ideals have many sources and are not explicable simply in terms of “corporeal
pleasures” and pains: the
intuitionists at least saw that much.
No comments:
Post a Comment