Suzanne Langer might not be the first person one would
associate with everyday aesthetics. Her
fundamental ideas are all associated with the word “virtual”: virtual object, virtual space, and virtual
time. But the virtual is deliberately
disassociated from the everyday. Unlike
Dewey, (and she is like Dewey in many respects) the virtual is not continuous
with everyday life. In this respect she
is more like Clive Bell. One could say
that her overall position combines Bell and Tolstoy: significant form and art as expression (she
uses both terms) although unlike Tolstoy and more like Collingwood, Langer
favors a cognitive approach to the expression of emotion. More on this later. In any case, she clearly believes that art is
autonomous, and this would seem to exclude everyday aesthetics. In fact, the autonomy position insofar as it
radically separates everyday life from art, makes everyday aesthetics difficult. It is thus not surprising that Langer is
dismissive of everyday aesthetics. She
considers music, for example, radically distinct from pleasurable non-musical
sound, and associates the later with the
pleasures of the senses of touch, taste and smell. She says, for example, that sound “as a sheer
sensory factor in experience, may be soothing or exciting, pleasing or
torturing; but so are the factors of
taste, smell, and touch.” (Ross 233) She
sees all these as “somatic influences” and believes that exploiting them is
“self-indulgence.” This approach would
not be friendly, for instance, to the ideas of Sherri Irwin. Langer strictly separates people who work in
these areas, whom she calls “mere epicures,” from artists whom, she believes,
are “torchbearers of culture” and “inspired creators.” So, “If music, patterned sound, had no other
office than to stimulate and soothe our nerves, pleasing our ears as
well-combined foods please our palates, it might be highly popular, but never
culturally important.” (223) Cooking schools should not be rated as
highly as music conservatories.
Langer, then, constantly stresses the
discontinuities between art and everyday life. Consider how she sees a picture:
“a picture …is an image, created for the first time out of things that
are not imagined, but quite realistic – canvas and paper…” (226)
Here we see how Langer is naïve about the phenomenological space of the
studio, where canvas and paper are seen by the artist as
having potential for creation and hence as part of a virtual space, the virtual
space of the working studio. The image
in the painting, to be sure, is created from this things which can be very
easily seen as without meaning content.
They can have a double reality, can be seen in one way or the other. They could not however be used in creation if
they did not have this phenomenological side.
Langer herself admits that the distinction between image and actuality
is functional: “real objects,
functioning in a way that is normal for images, may assume a purely imaginal
status.” (227)
So what then is an image? She says that a building “becomes an image when it presents itself
purely to our vision, i.e. as a sheer visual form instead of a locally and
practically related object.” (227) “We abstract its appearance from its material
existence” and then it becomes “simply a thing of vision” and “acquires a
different context.” There is some truth
in this, and yet it is more complicated than she makes out. One can say that its practical relations for
example are themselves transformed and carried up into the aesthetic realm and
so it is a mistake to think that material existence is always completely
distinct from imaginative experience, since material existence can be
imaginatively perceived and worked, and
acquiring a different context does not mean entirely losing the original
context. So there is something
problematic when Langer says that the painted canvas is not a new thing among
the things of the studio: it is indeed a
new thing, but let us not think of the other things of the studio as themselves
merely the objects of scientific or mathematical analysis. They too are not mere things. To be sure, imagination is more evidence in
the image: there is a kind of
intensification of imagination in the area of the image. The mistake can be seen in this quote: “even the forms are not phenomena in the
order of actual things, as spots on a tablecloth are; the forms in a design – no matter how abstract
– have a life that does not belong to mere spots.” (227)
What is deeply wrong here is that the spots on the tablecloth are not at
all mere spots. They are pot there as
part of a design, and so they too have a life, although no doubt not as
pronounced as the version of them we see in a painting by Matisse. So of course Langer is right that “something
arises in the process of arranging colors on a surface, something that is
created, not just gathered and set in new order: that is the image” but yet the new image in a
Matisse piggybacks on the new image on a less scale in the designs he uses as
subject matter. There is a continuity
between everyday life and art. Langer is
right that the painter is not just taking an arranging elements, that she/he is
creating a virtual space, and even that there is bracketing from the realm of
the practical, but not complete isolation or discontinuity.
Langer does not go as far in the direction of artistic
autonomy as, Clive Bell and the formalists however. Bell argues that art has nothing to do with
our everyday emotions. It only has to do
with that special aesthetic experience that we get from appropriately
apprehending something with significant form.
Art expresses emotion, not just the aesthetic emotion, but emotion in
general. But, unlike Tolstoy, art does not
express the particular emotion of the particular artist: it is
“not the symptomatic expression of feelings that beset the composer but
a symbolic expression of the forms of sentience as he understands them.” So the composer is not interested in expressing
his/her own feelings but rather what he/she “knows about” the inner life. The idea is to make a statement about human
sensibility in general through music (and art in general) as a symbol. Now that point I want to make here is that
Langer, in discussing individual art forms, begins to deconstruct the radical
discontinuity between art and life. She
already begins to move away from the formalists like Bell simply by observing
that art has to do with emotion. Keep
this summary in mind as we proceed:
“music is ‘significant form,’ and its significance is that of a symbol,
a highly articulated sensuous object, which by its dynamic structure can
express the forms of vital experience which language is peculiarly unfit to
convey.” (226) So “significant form” is not here tied to the
special “ecstatic” aesthetic experience in the way it is in Bell’s
formalism. Bell says that this
experience is like that of a mathematical discovery, or like religious
experience. It is transcendent in a
Platonic-like way. But for Langer
significant form is tied to the actual structures of our emotions. She is more like Aristotle: it captures and expresses universals, not
Platonic Forms. But she is very unlike
Dewey. Whereas Dewey stresses
continuity, she, again, stresses discontinuity. Now for my deconstruction. But please do not think of deconstruction as
a negative thing. I believe that Langer
provides us with help in solving problems in everyday aesthetics by way of this
deconstruction. Heidegger does something
similar, especially when he talks about the Greek temple, but Langer’s
formulation has the advantage of not being saddled with the Nazi baggage that
unfortunately Heidegger carries. Also,
she is not given to the often off-putting mystification we find in
Heidegger. I am beginning to reveal my
hand. My argument in short will be that
Langer, through her discussions first of Sculpture and then, even more so, when
she discusses Architecture, re-establishes continuity at least on one
level. And again she does so in a way
that can help us with what has been called the dilemma of everyday
aesthetics. Sculpture as with painting
creates what Langer calls virtual space, however unlike with painting, the
virtual space does not stop at the physical boundaries of the art object. The volume created “is more than the bulk of
the figure; it is a space made visible,
and is more than the area which the figure actually occupies.” (229) In
emphasizing the negative spaces and the spaces around the sculpture Langer essentially
expands the virtual space that she seeks to keep separate from everyday
life. Interestingly she is willing to
use the word “continuity” here, where she would not earlier: “The figure itself seems to have a sort of
continuity with the emptiness around it, however much its solid masses may
assert themselves as such.” (299) And further “the void enfolds it, and the
enfolding space has vital form as a continuation of the figure.” (299)
My point here is going to be related with an ongoing debate I have been
having with other everyday aesthetics.
My stress has been on the close relation between art aesthetics and
everyday aesthetics. What happens to the
space around the sculpture: it is
brought into the world of the work of art.
This is a problem in a way since the space then can be constituted in
two ways, for Langer, one as physical space of everyday life and one as virtual
space. But her understanding of physical
space is actually discursive, logical, scientific, and really not the space in which
we live. Whereas her virtual space is
the phenomenological (using Husserl’s sense of that term) space in which we
live: one that has emotional import. It is here I want to say something about
Langer’s actual closeness to Dewey, and this is by way of her notion of “vital
form.” One could say, in defense of
Langer, that the sculpture does not really move into the realm of the everyday
even though it goes beyond the physical object:
the empty space it “commands” is “part of the sculptural volume.” Let’s grant this. But things will be different when we come to
architecture. Here is an aside, related
to Dewey. Previously we observed that
Langer is closer to life than Bell in that she is committed to significant form
as having to do with the actual structure of our emotions, which surely are
tied to our lives. Further, she
emphasizes the “semblance of organism.”
Dewey stresses that we are live creatures interacting with our
environments. Langer tries to keep the
two radically separate, but interestingly the value of art is that it reflects
us by resembling ourselves as live organisms.
“Living organisms maintain themselves, resist change, strive to restore
their structure when it has been forcibly interfered with….organisms,
performing characteristic functions must have certain general forms, or
perish.” (229) Following Aristotle, once
again, she stresses that life has necessity, that only life “exhibits any
telos” and that the acorn strives to become the oak. Now she stresses that there is “nothing
actually organic about a work of sculpture” (230) and yet is gives us
“semblance of living form.”
Now for architecture.
The actual theory is a bit more complicated: “Architecture creates the semblance of that
World which is the counterpart of Self.
It is the total environment made visible.” It is not clear here how the environment made
visible is to be distinguished from the environment. The introduction of “Self” may indicate a
phenomenological point of view: we are
talking about the world as perceived by a self.
And as she observes that the “Self is collective” which probably simply
means that we perceive the world according to certain shared worldviews. This would explain why “the World is
communal.” But if this is so then the
World (ironically very like Heidegger’s concept of "world") really is the world
of everyday life experience. Thus
continuity is re-established. The only
world that is cut off is the world understood not phenomenologically but
discursively, i.e. the world as understood by science. That is a problem, I think, since it relies
on a continued dualism which would be unacceptable to a Dewayan, but we will
not address that here.
But things do get a bit confusing as when Langer says “as the actual environment of a being is a system of functional relations, so a virtual ‘environment,’ the created space of architecture, is a symbol of functional existence.” (230) What exactly can this mean: isn’t the virtual environment, the symbol of functional existence, exactly the phenomenological world in which we actual live and act: the world as we experience it? Here is an interesting implication: if that is so then the world surrounding architecture, basically the built environment, basically most of the world in which we live, is one that is infused with the spirit of architecture. But if that is true then the everyday is a collection of virtual spaces constituted by various architectural entities? Langer wants to stress the non-practical aspect of this space: “symbolic expression is something miles removed from provident planning or good arrangement.” (230) This seems to me just plain false. My architect brother, William Leddy, of Leddy, Maytum, Stacey designed the Roberts Campus for disability services in Berkeley, California. The work is both symbolically expressive and arranged well for people with disabilities: part of the symbolism is to accomplish this very arrangement. But I think that Langer is right when she says that symbolic expression “embodies the feeling, the rhythm, the passion or sobriety…by which all things are done.” Buildings create what she calls an “image of life” which is also “the visible semblance of an ‘ethnic domain’ by which I take her to mean not the domain of some ethnicity, like the Irish-Americans, but rather the domain of humanity since, for her, architecture is a “symbol of humanity to be found in the strength and interplay of forms.” What is ironic and strange here is that what is symbolized is identical with the symbol: for the symbol just is the virtual space created by architecture which is our space as expressive and lived. The two are both separate and dissolved into each other: and so we have a paradox…one might call it the paradox of architecture. Architecture, as least where we are talking about spaces constituted by architecture, is the space of everyday life. It is designed to accommodate everyday life aesthetics. As Langer puts it “the human environment, which is the counterpart of any human life, holds the imprint of a functional pattern; it is the complementary of organic form” which see sees in terms of the “metabolic pattern” of our both our feelings and our physical acts. But again as opposed to Langer, it is not just complementary or a counterpart; it is just exactly also where we live. To put it briefly: human life is in the human environment I do not deny that buildings create an illusion. In my book I described what I called the aesthetic aura. When we perceive our surrounding environment as having an “aura of significance” this can be called an illusion, if you wish, although this implies that what is seen is somehow less real: whereas in fact it is experienced as more real. So “illusion” is not my preferred term here. Instead of speaking as Langer does of creating “the illusion of an ethnic world” we should speak of creating an experience or way of experiencing the world in which there is heightened significance and in which the world, paradoxically, exemplifies itself. (See Nelson Goodman for further discussion of this.) Given this I agree with Langer that in architecture the place is “articulated by the imprint of human life” and that such a place “must seem organic, like a living form.” (230) The great modernist architects she mentions: Sullivan, Wright, Le Corbusier, all succeed in re-visioning the world through architecture in this organic way (although, to be sure, Le Corbusier, also like the machine metaphor, as when he spoke of a house as a machine for living.) I cannot agree however that life has “no relevance..to builder’s supplies.” As Dewey clearly showed, and also Heidegger, builder’s supplies are taken up into the virtual space of architecture and transformed by it. Let us not forget the thingliness of the thing, as Heidegger would put it. All of this said, I am in perfect accord with Langer’s idea that the place in this sense is destroyed when the work of architecture is destroyed. I will end by noting some of the ways in which Langer allows the work of architecture to reach out even further into the world, in terms of continuity with everyday life, than the work of sculpture. As she puts it: “its virtual domain may include terraces and gardens, or rows of sphinxes…” and further “sea and sky may fill the intervals between its columns and be gathered to its space.” This point is, of course, remarkably similar to Heidegger on the temple. The “ethnic domain” is perhaps better described by her as an “atmosphere” created by architecture. I just cannot accept her separation of the utility of the building from its “semblance.” Or her conviction that hot water heaters are irrelevant to architecture.
But things do get a bit confusing as when Langer says “as the actual environment of a being is a system of functional relations, so a virtual ‘environment,’ the created space of architecture, is a symbol of functional existence.” (230) What exactly can this mean: isn’t the virtual environment, the symbol of functional existence, exactly the phenomenological world in which we actual live and act: the world as we experience it? Here is an interesting implication: if that is so then the world surrounding architecture, basically the built environment, basically most of the world in which we live, is one that is infused with the spirit of architecture. But if that is true then the everyday is a collection of virtual spaces constituted by various architectural entities? Langer wants to stress the non-practical aspect of this space: “symbolic expression is something miles removed from provident planning or good arrangement.” (230) This seems to me just plain false. My architect brother, William Leddy, of Leddy, Maytum, Stacey designed the Roberts Campus for disability services in Berkeley, California. The work is both symbolically expressive and arranged well for people with disabilities: part of the symbolism is to accomplish this very arrangement. But I think that Langer is right when she says that symbolic expression “embodies the feeling, the rhythm, the passion or sobriety…by which all things are done.” Buildings create what she calls an “image of life” which is also “the visible semblance of an ‘ethnic domain’ by which I take her to mean not the domain of some ethnicity, like the Irish-Americans, but rather the domain of humanity since, for her, architecture is a “symbol of humanity to be found in the strength and interplay of forms.” What is ironic and strange here is that what is symbolized is identical with the symbol: for the symbol just is the virtual space created by architecture which is our space as expressive and lived. The two are both separate and dissolved into each other: and so we have a paradox…one might call it the paradox of architecture. Architecture, as least where we are talking about spaces constituted by architecture, is the space of everyday life. It is designed to accommodate everyday life aesthetics. As Langer puts it “the human environment, which is the counterpart of any human life, holds the imprint of a functional pattern; it is the complementary of organic form” which see sees in terms of the “metabolic pattern” of our both our feelings and our physical acts. But again as opposed to Langer, it is not just complementary or a counterpart; it is just exactly also where we live. To put it briefly: human life is in the human environment I do not deny that buildings create an illusion. In my book I described what I called the aesthetic aura. When we perceive our surrounding environment as having an “aura of significance” this can be called an illusion, if you wish, although this implies that what is seen is somehow less real: whereas in fact it is experienced as more real. So “illusion” is not my preferred term here. Instead of speaking as Langer does of creating “the illusion of an ethnic world” we should speak of creating an experience or way of experiencing the world in which there is heightened significance and in which the world, paradoxically, exemplifies itself. (See Nelson Goodman for further discussion of this.) Given this I agree with Langer that in architecture the place is “articulated by the imprint of human life” and that such a place “must seem organic, like a living form.” (230) The great modernist architects she mentions: Sullivan, Wright, Le Corbusier, all succeed in re-visioning the world through architecture in this organic way (although, to be sure, Le Corbusier, also like the machine metaphor, as when he spoke of a house as a machine for living.) I cannot agree however that life has “no relevance..to builder’s supplies.” As Dewey clearly showed, and also Heidegger, builder’s supplies are taken up into the virtual space of architecture and transformed by it. Let us not forget the thingliness of the thing, as Heidegger would put it. All of this said, I am in perfect accord with Langer’s idea that the place in this sense is destroyed when the work of architecture is destroyed. I will end by noting some of the ways in which Langer allows the work of architecture to reach out even further into the world, in terms of continuity with everyday life, than the work of sculpture. As she puts it: “its virtual domain may include terraces and gardens, or rows of sphinxes…” and further “sea and sky may fill the intervals between its columns and be gathered to its space.” This point is, of course, remarkably similar to Heidegger on the temple. The “ethnic domain” is perhaps better described by her as an “atmosphere” created by architecture. I just cannot accept her separation of the utility of the building from its “semblance.” Or her conviction that hot water heaters are irrelevant to architecture.
No comments:
Post a Comment